Thought-Factory.net Philosophical Conversations Public Opinion philosophy.com Junk for code
hegel
"When philosophy paints its grey in grey then has a shape of life grown old. By philosophy's grey in grey it cannot be rejuvenated but only understood. The owl of Minerva spreads its wings only with the falling of dusk." -- G.W.F. Hegel, 'Preface', Philosophy of Right.
RECENT ENTRIES
SEARCH
ARCHIVES
Library
Links - weblogs
Links - Political Rationalities
Links - Resources: Philosophy
Public Discussion
Resources
Cafe Philosophy
Philosophy Centres
Links - Resources: Other
Links - Web Connections
Other
www.thought-factory.net
'Constant revolutionizing of production, uninterrupted disturbance of all social conditions, everlasting uncertainity and agitation distinquish the bourgeois epoch from all earlier ones ... All that is solid melts into air, all that is holy is profaned.' Marx

Arendt: politics as critique of modernity « Previous | |Next »
October 31, 2004


This
is interesting terms of the interpretation of Foucault's governmentality as a rupture with traditional (juridical ) conceptions of the political. Dana Villa's new book, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political, provides an account of the political thought of Heidegger and Arendt from the perspective of a politics marked by the philosophical critique of modernity.

According to Charles Bambach, Villa focuses on the way that Arendt's whole style of reading and appropriating the Western philosophical tradition:


"... is determined by her adherence to two basic modes of interpretation from Being and Time (1927): retrieval (Wiederholung) and de-construction (Abbau). Simply put, like Heidegger, Arendt's fundamental strategy is to read the tradition not in a spirit of reverence or with the aim of repetition; instead, she attempts to dismantle philosophical concepts, to loosen them from their sedimented and hypostatized strata in order to free them up for a radical kind of retrieval that rethinks their essence from an ontological perspective. Or rather, she wishes to dispense with the whole notion of any subject-centered "perspective" and recover not concepts, but a certain way of being-in-the-world."

Arendt argues against Aristotle. Her theory of political action attempts a radical reconceptualization of action, one that proceeds, in part, through a critique and transformation of Aristotelian praxis. Bambich says that whereas Aristotle understands political activity on the model of poiesis as a kind of "crafting" of political life:

"...Arendt breaks with him in order to recover the freedom of political action which she finds in the pre-Socratic tradition. For her, both Plato and Aristotle come to see lawmaking and city-building [politcs] as.... as a means and not an end. As Arendt understands it, while Aristotle asserts on the one hand that praxis is valuable in and of itself, on the other, like Plato he makes it subservient to a goal: the "highest good." And yet by virtue of her deconstructive reading of Aristotle.....Arendt comes to define political action as the last realm of activity in which the human being can experience freedom."

For Arendt in modernity which she equates with the European project of technical-instrumentalist activity since the seventeenth century), there are three types of the vita activa: "labor" (which she describes as a cyclical and repetitious "animal" activity tied to the sheer biological necessity of survival), "work" (which she defines as a "human" activity that involves one in the making, producing, and instrumental fabrication of poiesis), and "action" (which she equates with Aristotle's notion of an activity that has no end outside of itself and is a genuine form of praxis).

She argues that the modern individual gets borne by the ceaseless project of Cartesian mastery and the possession of nature. As a result, s/he is transformed into homo faber, that active being whose finished products become means for the inevitable end of "the limitless instrumentalization of everything that exists." All contemporary life winds up being caught within this instrumentalist mode of being that leads humanity to desire ever more power and control over the world of nature.

This is a very familar critique, one that was developed by the Frankfurt School--Adorno, Horkheimer and Habermas. So what was different about Arendt's political critique of modernity?

Part Two of Villa's book suggests that the difference lies in the ontological dimension of Arendt's critique of modernity. This was influenced by Heidegger's critique of Cartesian subjectivity and its corresponding instrumentalism. Bambich says that Arendt follows Heidegger in deconstructing:


"...the Cartesian will to mastery (reconfigured as Nietzsche's will to power), Heidegger pointed to a new ontological sense of freedom--not of the self-grounding subject, but of human Dasein as a form of "being-in-the-world"... For Arendt, this implied that human freedom was marked by finitude, contingency, and worldliness-properties that reinforced the public character of existence rather than the privatized, interior, and abstract world of the Cartesian subject."

Arendt then puts Heidegger into question by challenging his emphasis on "authenticity" and private life. Villa argues that Arendt "politicizes" Heidegger's existential lexicon by inverting the Heideggerian identification of authenticity with interiority and inauthenticity with the public world of the "they-self." Arendt's argument is Heidegger's brilliant critique of modern subjectivity is limited by the privileging of the authentically interior vita contemplativa against the inauthentically public vita activa.

On Villa's account Arendt appropriates Heidegger by twisting, displacing, and reinterpreting his thought in ways designed to illuminate a range of exceedingly un-Heideggerian issues; the nature of political action, the positive ontological role of the public realm, the nature of political judgement, and the conditions for an antiauthoritarian, antifoundational, democratic politics.

| Posted by Gary Sauer-Thompson at 12:41 PM | | Comments (3)
Comments

Comments

Gary

A Few years ago I read parts of Villa's book. It is very good at capturing many of the subtle connections between Arendt and Heidegger's thought. But it does point to what I believe is a severe limitation of Arendt's rethinking of "the political." That is her indebtedness to Heidegger's notion of self-disclosure. Freedom is manifested in the words and deeds that are revealed in the public space, what Arendt calls the "space of appearance." This aesthetic notion of freedom seems to severely limit what is considered legitimate political action. Her famous exclusion of socio-economic issues from the realm of politics would be a case in point.

Alain,
Alas, I have yet to read the Villa book, even though it came out around 1996. I struggled with Heidegger instead. The book is on order.

I have, however, read bits and pieces of her work off and on. I guess I understand Arendt in terms the central strands in civic republicanism-- freedom, civic virtues, participation, the common good, citizenship and public versus private interests. So the good life for a human being, the life in which the highest and the most human capacities are exercised, is the political life.

I too have a similar problem with the emphasis on politics as performance, and her exclusion of the socio-economic issues from the realm of politics.

However, I like her emphasis on judgement, the public sphere, creating spaces of freedom through collective action, the positive values of political participation, citizenship and the limits of negative freedom.

It seems to me that Arendt, along with Charles Taylor,has helped to recover a classical civic republicanism as a main alternative to liberalism.

In doing so she helps to counter the degradation of politics in liberal democracies into a means for the exercise of individual liberty, the pursuit of private interest, or the provision for each individual's liberty and private interest by means of wealth creation.

What is recovered is the idea of the political as collective deliberation in the public realm, the giving of speeches in the presence of one's fellow citizens, and in persuading and being persuaded in turn.

It is what happens in the Senate in Australia and the US and it is mocked.

Gary

I completely agree with your assessment of Arendt's positive retrieval of poltical discourse. My reaction was intially critical because, for all of her great insight, she always struck me as too much of an elitist. I realize this may not be fair, especially in light of her early criticisms of zionism which are very concrete. But nevertheless, she always seems to be romanticizing the Greco-Roman experience, holding it up as a possibility that is only rarely seen today. Again, since I have not read Arendt in many years, this may not be a fair criticism.

I recall another great book on Arendt was written by Richard Bernstein: Hannah Arendt and the Jewish Question. Its basic argument is that much of Arendt's thinking about the political realm was influenced by her experience as a stateless Jew, and as a response to the Holocaust.